Environmental Ethics:
Values in and Duties to the Natural World
by
Holmes Rolston, III
Published in: The Broken
Circle: Ecology, Economics, Ethics. F. Herbert Bormann
and Stephen R. Kellert, Eds. Yale University Press, New
Haven 1991. ISBN 0-300-04976-5
Environmental ethics stretches classical ethics to a
breaking point. All ethics seeks an appropriate respect for
life. But we do not just need a humanist ethic applied to
the environment, analogously to the ways we have needed one
for business, law, medicine, technology, international
development, or nuclear disarmament. Respect for life
demands an ethic concerned about human welfare, like the
others and now concerning the environment. But environmental
ethics in a deeper sense stands on a frontier, as radically
theoretical as it is applied. Alone, it asks whether there
can be nonhuman objects of duty.
Neither theory nor practice
elsewhere needs values outside of human subjects, but
environmental ethics must be more biologically objective--nonanthropocentric.
It challenges the separation of science and ethics, trying
to reform a science that finds nature value free and an
ethics that assumes that only humans count morally.
Environmental ethics seeks to escape relativism in ethics,
to discover a way past culturally based ethics. However much
our world views, ethics included, are embedded in our
cultural heritages, and thereby theory-laden and value-laden,
all of us know that a natural world exists apart from human
cultures. Humans interact with nature. Environmental ethics
is the only ethics that breaks out of culture. It has to
evaluate nature, both the nature that mixes with culture and
wild nature, and to judge duty thereby. After environmental
ethics, you will no longer be the humanist you once were.
Environmental ethics
requires risk. Environmental ethics explores poorly charted
terrain, where it is easy to get lost. One must hazard the
kind of insight that first looks like foolishness. Some
approach environmental ethics with a smile--expecting rights
for rocks and chicken liberation, misplaced concern for
chipmunks and daisies. Elsewhere, you think, ethicists deal
with sober concerns: medical ethics, business ethics,
justice in public affairs, questions of life and death,
peace and war. But the questions here are no less serious:
the degradation of the environment poses as great a threat
to life as nuclear war, and a more probable tragedy.
Higher Animals
Logically and
psychologically, the best and easiest breakthrough past the
traditional boundaries of interhuman ethics is made
confronting higher animals. Animals defend their lives; they
have a good of their own, suffer pains and pleasures like
ourselves. Human moral concern should at least cross over
into the domain of animal experience. This boundary crossing
is also dangerous because if made only psychologically and
not biologically the would-be environmental ethicist may be
too disoriented to travel further. The promised
environmental ethics will degenerate into a mammal ethics.
We certainly need an ethic for animals, but that is only one
level of concern in a comprehensive environmental ethics.
One might expect classical
ethics to have sifted well an ethics for animals. Our
ancestors did not think about endangered species,
ecosystems, acid rain, or the ozone layer, but they lived in
closer association with wild and domestic animals than do
we. Hunters track wounded deer, the rancher who lets his
horses starve is prosecuted. Still, until recently, the
scientific, humanistic centuries since the so-called
Enlightenment have not been sensitive ones for animals,
owing to the Cartesian legacy. Animals were mindless, living
matter; biology has been mechanistic. Even psychology,
rather than defending animal experience, has been
behaviorist. Philosophy has protested little, concerned to
locate values in human experiences at the same time that it
dis-spirited and devalued nature. Across several centuries
of hard science and humanist ethics there has been little
compassion for animals.
The progress of science
itself smeared the human-nonhuman boundary line. Animal
anatomy, biochemistry, cognition, perception, experience,
and behavior, and evolutionary history are kin to our own.
Animals have no immortal souls, but then persons may not
either, or beings with souls may not be the only kind that
count morally. Ethical progress further smeared the
boundary. Sensual pleasures are a good thing, ethics should
be egalitarian nonarbitrary, nondiscriminator y. There are
ample scientific grounds that animals enjoy pleasures and
suffer pains; and ethically no grounds to value these in
humans and not in animals. So there has been a vigorous
reassessment of human duties to sentient life. The world
cheered in the fall of 1988 when humans rescued two whales
from the winter ice.
"Respect their right to
life." A sign in Rocky Mountain National Park enjoins humans
not to harass bighorn sheep. "The question is not, Can they
reason, nor Can they talk? but, Can they suffer?" said
Jeremy Bentham, insisting that animal welfare counts too.
The Park Service sign and Bentham's question increase
sensitivity by extending rights and hedonist goods to
animals. The gain is a vital breakthrough past humans, and
the first lesson in environmental ethics has been learned.
But the risk is a moral extension that expands rights as far
as mammals and not much further, a psychologically based
ethic that counts only felt experience. We respect life in
our nonhuman but near-human animal cousins, a semi-anthropic
and still quite subjective ethics. Justice remains a concern
for just-us subjects. There has, in fact, not been much
theoretical breakthrough, no paradigm shift.
Lacking that, there is
anomaly and conceptual strain. When we try to use culturally
extended rights and psychologically based utilities to
protect the flora or even the insentient fauna, to protect
endangered species or ecosystems, we can only stammer.
Indeed, we get lost trying to protect bighorns, because, in
the wild, the cougar is not respecting the rights or
utilities of the sheep she slays, and, in culture, humans
slay sheep and eat them regularly, while humans have every
right not to be eaten by either humans or cougars. There are
no rights in the wild, and nature is indifferent to the
welfare of particular animals. A bison fell through the ice
into a river in Yellowstone Park; the environmental ethic
there, letting nature take its course, forbade would-be
rescuers from either saving or mercy killing the suffering
animal. A drowning human would have been saved at once.
Perhaps it was a mistake to save those whales.
The ethics by extension now
seems too nondiscriminating; we are unable to separate an
ethics for humans from an ethics for wildlife. To treat wild
animals with compassion learned in culture does not
appreciate their wildness. Man, said Socrates, is the
political animal; humans maximally are what they are in
culture, where the natural selection pressures (impressively
productive in ecosystems) are relaxed without detriment to
the species Homo sapiens, and indeed with great
benefit to its member persons. Wild animals cannot enter
culture; they do not have that capacity. They cannot acquire
language at sufficient levels to take part in culture; they
cannot make their clothing, or build fires, much less read
books or receive an education. Animals can, by human
adoption, receive some of the protections of culture, which
happens when we domesticate them, but neither pets nor food
animals enter the culture that shelters them.
Worse, such cultural
protection can work to their detriment; their wildness is
made over into a human artifact as food or pet animal. A cow
does not have the integrity of a deer, a poodle that of a
wolf. Culture is a good thing for humans, often a bad thing
for animals. Their biology and ecology--neither justice nor
charity, nor rights nor welfare--provides the benchmark for
an ethics.
Culture does make a relevant
ethical difference, and environmental ethics has different
criteria from interhuman ethics. Can they talk? and, Can
they reason?, indicating cultural capacities, are relevant
questions, not just, Can they suffer? "Equality" is a
positive word in ethics, "discriminatory" a pejorative one.
On the other hand, simplistic reduction is a failing in the
philosophy of science and epistemology; to be
"discriminating" is desirable in logic and value theory.
Something about treating humans as equals with bighorns and
cougars seems to "reduce" humans to merely animal levels of
value, a "no more" counterpart in ethics of the "nothing
but" fallacy often met in science. Humans are "nothing but"
naked apes. Something about treating sheep and cougars as
the equals of humans seems to elevate them unnaturally,
unable to value them for what they are. There is something
insufficiently discriminating in such judgments--species
blind in a bad sense, blind to the real differences between
species, valuational differences that do count morally. To
the contrary, a discriminating ethicist will insist on
preserving the differing richness of valuational complexity,
wherever found. Compassionate respect for life in its
suffering is only part of the analysis.
Two tests of discrimination
are pains and diet. It might be thought that pain is a bad
thing, whether in nature or culture. Perhaps when dealing
with humans in culture additional levels of value and
utility must be protected by conferring rights that do not
exist in the wilds, but meanwhile at least we should
minimize animal suffering. That is indeed a worthy
imperative in culture where animals are removed from nature
and bred, but it may be misguided where animals remain in
ecosystems. When the bighorn sheep of Yellowstone caught
pinkeye, blinded, injured, and starving in result, 300
bighorns, over half the herd, perished. Wildlife
veterinarians wanted to treat the disease, as they would
have in any domestic herd, and as they did with Colorado
bighorns infected with an introduced lungworm, but the
Yellowstone ethicists left them to suffer, seemingly not
respecting their life.
Had these ethicists no
mercy? They knew rather that, while intrinsic pain is a bad
thing whether in humans or in sheep, pain in ecosystems is
instrumental pain, through which the sheep are naturally
selected for a more satisfactory adaptive fit. Pain in a
medically skilled culture is pointless, once the alarm to
health is sounded, but pain operates functionally in
bighorns in their niche, even after it becomes no longer in
the interests of the pained individual. To have interfered
in the interests of the blinded sheep would have weakened
the species. Even the question, Can they suffer? is not as
simple as Bentham thought. What we ought to do
depends on what is. The is of nature differs
significantly from the is of culture, even when
similar suffering is present in both.
At this point some ethicists
will insist that least in culture we can minimize animal
pain, and that will constrain our diet. There is predation
in nature; humans evolved as omnivores. But humans, the only
moral animals, should refuse to participate in the meat
eating phase of their ecology, just as they refuse to play
the game merely by the rules of natural selection. Humans do
not look to the behavior of wild animals as an ethical guide
in other matters (marriage, truth-telling, promise-keeping,
justice, charity). Why should they justify their dietary
habits by watching what animals do?
But the difference is that
these other matters are affairs of culture; these are
person-to-person events, not events at all in spontaneous
nature. By contrast, eating is omnipresent in wild nature;
humans eat because they are in nature, not because they are
in culture. Eating animals is not an event between persons,
but is a human-to-animal event; and the rules for this come
from the ecosystems in which humans evolved and have no duty
to remake. Humans, then, can model their dietary habits from
their ecosystems, though they cannot and should not so model
their interpersonal justice or charity. When eating they
ought to minimize animal suffering, but they have no duty to
revise trophic pyramids whether in nature or culture. The
boundary between animals and humans has not been rubbed out
after all; only what was a boundary line has been smeared
into a boundary zone. We have discovered that animals count
morally, though not yet solved the challenge of how to count
them.
Animals enjoy psychological
lives, subjective experiences, felt interests satisfied,
intrinsic values that count morally when humans encounter
them. But the pains, pleasures, interests, and welfare of
individual animals are only one of the considerations in a
more complex environmental ethic that cannot be reached by
conferring rights on them or by a hedonist calculus, however
far extended. We have to travel further into a more
biologically based ethics.
Organisms
If we are to respect all
life, we have still another boundary to cross, from zoology
to botany, from sentient to insentient life. In Yosemite
National Park for almost a century humans entertained
themselves by driving through a tunnel cut in a giant
sequoia. Two decades ago the Wawona tree, weakened by the
cut, blew down in a storm. People said: Cut us another
drive-through sequoia. The Yosemite environmental ethic,
deepening over the years, said: No! You ought not to
mutilate majestic sequoias for amusement. Respect their
life! Indeed, some ethicists count the value of redwoods so
highly that they will spike redwoods, lest they be cut. In
the Rawah Wilderness in alpine Colorado, old signs read,
"Please leave the flowers for others to enjoy." When they
rotted out, the new signs urged a less humanist ethic: "Let
the flowers live!"
But trees and flowers cannot
care, so why should we? We are not considering animals that
are close kin, nor can they suffer or experience anything.
Plants are not valuers with preferences that can be
satisfied or frustrated. It seems odd to claim that plants
need our sympathy, odd to ask that we should consider their
point of view. They have no subjective life, only objective
life.
Perhaps the questions are
wrong, because they are coming out of the old paradigm. We
are at a critical divide; you see why I earlier warned that
those who seek only to extend a humanist ethic to mammal
cousins will get lost. Seeing no moral landmarks, they may
turn back to more familiar terrain. Afraid of the
naturalistic fallacy, they will say that people should enjoy
letting flowers live or that it is silly to cut
drive-through sequoias, aesthetically more excellent for
humans to appreciate both for what they are. But these
ethically conservative reasons really do not understand what
biological conservation is in the deepest sense.
It takes ethical courage to
go on, a bio-logic past a hedonist, humanist logic. Pains,
pleasures, psychological experience will no further be
useful categories, but--lest some think that from here on I
as a philosopher become illogical lose all ethical
sense--let us orient ourselves by extending logical,
propositional, cognitive, and normative categories into
biology. Nothing matters to a tree, but much is vital.
An organism is a
spontaneous, self-maintaining system, sustaining and
reproducing itself, executing its program, making a way
through the world, checking against performance by means of
responsive capacities with which to measure success. It can
reckon with vicissitudes, opportunities, and adversities
that the world presents. Something more than physical
causes, even when less than sentience, is operating within
every organism. There is information superintending
the causes, without it the organism would collapse into a
sand heap. This information is a modern equivalent of what
Aristotle called formal and final causes; it gives the
organism a telos, "end," a kind of (nonfelt) goal.
Organisms have ends, although not always ends-in-view.
All this cargo is carried by
the DNA, essentially a linguistic molecule. By a
serial "reading" of the DNA, a polypeptide chain is
synthesized, such that its sequential structure determines
the bioform into which it will fold. Ever-lengthening
chains (like ever-longer sentences), are organized into
genes (like paragraphs and chapters). Diverse proteins,
lipids, carbohydrates, enzymes--all the life structures are
"written into" the genetic library. The DNA is thus a
logical set, not less than a biological set, informed as
well as formed. Organisms use a sort of symbolic logic, use
these molecular shapes as symbols of life. The novel
resourcefulness lies in the epistemic content conserved,
developed, and thrown forward to make biological resources
out of the physicochemical sources. This executive steering
core is cybernetic--partly a special kind of cause and
effect system, and partly something more: partly a
historical information system discovering and evaluating
ends so as to map and make a way through the world, partly a
system of significances attached to operations, pursuits,
resources. In this sense, the genome is a set of
conservation molecules.
The genetic set is really a
propositional set--to choose a provocative
term--recalling how the Latin propositum is an
assertion, a set task, a theme, a plan, a proposal, a
project, as well as a cognitive statement. From this it is
also a motivational set, unlike human books, since these
life motifs are set to drive the movement from genotypic
potential to phenotypic expression. Given a chance, these
molecules seek organic self-expression. They thus proclaim
a life way, and with this an organism, unlike an inert rock,
claims the environment as source and sink, from which to
abstract energy and materials and into which to excrete
them. It "takes advantage" of its environment. Life thus
arises out of earthen sources (as do rocks), but life turns
back on its sources to make resources out of them (unlike
rocks). An acorn becomes an oak; the oak stands on its own.
So far we have only
description. We begin to pass to value when we recognize
that the genetic set is a normative set; it
distinguishes between what is and what ought to
be. This does not mean that the organism is a moral
system, for there are no moral agents in nature; but the
organism is an axiological, evaluative system. So the oak
grows, reproduces, repairs its wounds, and resists death.
The physical state that the organism seeks, idealized in its
programmatic form, is a valued state. Value is
present in this achievement. Vital seems a better
word for it than biological. We are not dealing
simply with another individual defending its solitary life
but with an individual having situated fitness in an
ecosystem. Still, we want to affirm that the living
individual, taken as a "point experience" in the web of
interconnected life, is per se an intrinsic value.
A life is defended for what
it is in itself, without necessary further contributory
reference, although, given the structure of all ecosystems,
such lives necessarily do have further contributory
reference. The organism has something it is conserving,
something for which it is standing: its life. Organisms have
their own standards, fit into their niche though they must.
They promote their own realization, at the same time that
they track an environment. They have a technique, a
know-how. Every organism has a good-of-its-kind; it
defends its own kind as a good kind. In that sense,
as soon as one knows what a giant sequoia tree is, one knows
the biological identity that is sought and conserved.
There seems no reason why
such own-standing normative organisms are not morally
significant. A moral agent deciding his or her behavior
ought to take account of the consequences for other
evaluative systems. Within the community of moral agents
one has not merely to ask whether x is a normative
system, but, since the norms are at personal option, to
judge the norm. But within the biotic community organisms
are amoral normative systems, and there are no cases where
an organism seeks a good of its own that is morally
reprehensible. The distinction between having a good of its
kind and being a good kind vanishes, so far as any faulting
of the organism is concerned. To this extent, everything
with a good of its kind is a good kind and thereby has
intrinsic value.
One might say that an
organism is a bad organism if, during the course of pressing
its normative expression, it upsets the ecosystem or causes
widespread disease. Remember though, that an organism
cannot be a good kind without situated environmental
fitness. By natural selection the kind of goods to which it
is genetically programmed must mesh with its ecosystemic
role. Despite the ecosystem as a perpetual contest of goods
in dialectic and exchange, it is difficult to say that any
organism is a bad kind in this instrumental sense either.
The misfits are extinct, or soon will be. In spontaneous
nature any species that preys upon, parasitizes, competes
with, or crowds another will be a bad kind from the narrow
perspective of its victim or competitor.
But if we enlarge that
perspective it typically becomes difficult to say that any
species is a bad kind overall in the ecosystem. An "enemy"
may even be good for the "victimized" species, though
harmful to individual members of it, as when predation keeps
the deer herd healthy. Beyond this, the "bad kinds"
typically play useful roles in population control, in
symbiotic relationships, or in providing opportunities for
other species. The Chlamydia microbe is a bad kind
from the perspective of the bighorns, but when one thing
dies, something else lives. After the pinkeye outbreak, the
golden eagle population in Yellowstone flourished, preying
on the bighorn carcasses. For them Chlamydia is a
good kind instrumentally.
Some biologist-philosophers
will say that, even though an organism evolves to have a
situated environmental fitness, not all such situations are
good arrangements; some can be clumsy or bad. True, the
vicissitudes of historical evolution do sometimes result in
ecological webs that are suboptimal solutions, within the
biologically limited possibilities and powers of interacting
organisms. Still, such systems have been selected over
millennia for functional stability; and at least the burden
of proof is on a human evaluator to say why any natural kind
is a bad kind and ought not to call forth admiring respect.
Something may be a good kind intrinsically but a bad kind
instrumentally in the system; these will be anomalous cases,
however, with selection pressures against them. These claims
about good kinds do not say that things are perfect kinds,
or that there can be no better ones, only that natural kinds
are good kinds until proven otherwise.
In fact, what is almost
invariably meant by a "bad" kind is that an organism is
instrumentally bad when judged from the viewpoint of human
interests, often with the further complication that human
interests have disrupted natural systems. "Bad" as so used
is an anthropocentric word; there is nothing at all
biological or ecological about it, and so it has no force
evaluating objective nature, however much humanist force it
may sometimes have.
A really vital ethic
respects all life, not just animal pains and pleasures, much
less just human preferences. In the Rawahs, the old signs,
"Leave the flowers for others to enjoy," were application
signs using an old, ethically conservative, humanistic
ethic. The new ones invite a change of reference frame--a
wilder, more logical because more biological ethic, a
radical ethic that goes down to the roots of life, that
really is conservative because it understands biological
conservation at depths. What the injunction, "Let the
flowers live!" means is: "Daisies, marsh-marigolds,
geraniums, larkspurs are evaluative systems that conserve
goods of their kind, and, in the absence of evidence to the
contrary, are good kinds. There are trails here by which
you may enjoy these flowers. Is there any reason why your
human interests should not also conserve these good kinds?"
A drive-through sequoia causes no suffering; it is not
cruel. But it is callous and insensitive to the wonder of
life.
Species
Sensitivity to this wonder,
however, can sometimes make an environmental ethicist seem
callous. On San Clemente Island, the U.S. Fish and Wildlife
Service and the Natural Resources Office of the U.S. Navy
planned to shoot two thousand feral goats to save three
endangered plant species, Malacothamnus clementinus,
Castilleja grisea, Delphinium kinkiense, of
which the surviving individuals numbered only a few dozens.
After a protest, some goats were trapped and relocated. But
trapping all was impossible and many thousands were killed.
We count plant species more than mammal lives, a few plants
more than thousands of goats.
Those who wish to rare
species of big cats to the wilds have asked about killing
genetically inbred, inferior cats, presently held in zoos,
in order to make space available for the cats needed to
reconstruct and maintain a population genetically more
likely to survive upon release. All the Siberian tigers in
zoos in North America are descendants of seven animals; if
these were replaced by others nearer to the wild type and
with more genetic variability, the species could be saved in
the wild. When we move to the level of species, we may kill
individuals for the good of their kind.
Or we may now refuse to let
nature take its course. The Yellowstone ethicists let the
bison drown, callous to its suffering; they let the blinded
bighorns die. But in the spring of 1984 a sow grizzly and
her three cubs walked across the ice of Yellowstone Lake to
Frank Island, two miles from shore. They stayed several days
to feast on two elk carcasses, when the ice bridge melted.
Soon afterward, they were starving on an island too small to
support them. This time the Yellowstone ethicists promptly
rescued the grizzlies and released them on the mainland, in
order to protect an endangered species. They were not
rescuing individual bears so much as saving the species.
Coloradans are considering
whether to build the Two Forks Dam to supply urban Denver
with water. This would require destroying a canyon and
altering the Platte River flow, with many negative
environmental consequences, including further endangering
the whooping crane and endangering a butterfly, the Pawnee
montane skipper. Elsewhere in the state, water development
threatens several fish species, including the humpback chub,
which requires the turbulent spring runoff stopped by dams.
Environmental ethics doubts whether the good of humans who
wish more water for development, both for industry and for
bluegrass lawns, warrants endangering species of cranes,
butterflies, fish.
A species exists; a species
ought to exist. An environmental ethics must make these
claims and move from biology to ethics with care. Species
exist only instantiated in individuals, yet are as real as
individual plants or animals. The claim that there are
specific forms of life historically maintained in their
environments over time seems as certain as anything else we
believe about the empirical world. At times biologists
revise the theories and taxa with which they map these
forms, but species are not so much like lines of latitude
and longitude as like mountains and rivers, phenomena
objectively there to be mapped. The edges of these natural
kinds will sometimes be fuzzy, to some extent discretionary.
One species will slide into another over evolutionary time.
But it does not follow from the fact that speciation is
sometimes in progress that species are merely made up, not
found as evolutionary lines with identity in time as well as
space.
A consideration of species
is revealing and challenging because it offers a
biologically based counterexample to the focus on
individuals--typically sentient and usually persons--so
characteristic in classical ethics. In an evolutionary
ecosystem, it is not mere individuality that counts, but the
species is also significant because it is a dynamic life
form maintained over time. The individual represents
(re-presents) a species in each new generation. It is a
token of a type, and the type is more important than the
token.
A species lacks moral
agency, reflective self-awareness, sentience, or organic
individuality. The older, conservative ethic will be
tempted to say that specific-level processes cannot count
morally. Duties must attach to singular lives, most
evidently those with a self, or some analogue to this. In
an individual organism, the organs report to a center; the
good of a whole is defended. The members of a species
report to no center. A species has no self. It is not a
bounded singular. There is no analogue to the nervous
hookups or circulatory flows that characterize the organism.
But singularity,
centeredness, selfhood, individuality, are not the only
processes to which duty attaches. A more radically
conservative ethic knows that having a biological identity
reasserted genetically over time is as true of the species
as of the individual. Identity need not attach solely to the
centered organism; it can persist as a discrete pattern over
time. Thinking this way, the life that the individual has is
something passing through the individual as much as
something it intrinsically possesses. The individual is
subordinate to the species, not the other way around. The
genetic set, in which is coded the telos, is as
evidently the property of the species as of the individual
through which it passes. A consideration of species strains
any ethic fixed on individual organisms, much less on
sentience or persons. But the result can be biologically
sounder, though it revises what was formerly thought
logically permissible or ethically binding. When ethics is
informed by this kind of biology, it is appropriate to
attach duty dynamically to the specific form of life.
The species line is the
vital living system, the whole, of which individual
organisms are the essential parts. The species too has its
integrity, its individuality, its "right to life" (if we
must use the rhetoric of rights); and it is more important
to protect this vitality than to protect individual
integrity. The right to life, biologically speaking, is an
adaptive fit that is right for life, that survives over
millennia, and this generates at least a presumption that
species in niche are good right where they are, and
therefore that it is right for humans to let them be, to let
them evolve.
Processes of value that we
earlier found in an organic individual reappear at the
specific level: defending a particular form of life,
pursuing a pathway through the world, resisting death
(extinction), regeneration maintaining a normative identity
over time, creative resilience discovering survival skills.
It is as logical to say that the individual is the species'
way of propagating itself as to say that the embryo or egg
is the individual's way of propagating itself. The dignity
resides in the dynamic form; the individual inherits this,
exemplifies it, and passes it on. If, at the specific level,
these processes are just as evident, or even more so, what
prevents duties arising at that level? The appropriate
survival unit is the appropriate level of moral concern.
A shutdown of the life
stream is the most destructive event possible. The wrong
that humans are doing, or allowing to happen through
carelessness, is stopping the historical vitality of life,
the flow of natural kinds. Every extinction is an
incremental decay in this stopping life, no small thing.
Every extinction is a kind of superkilling. It kills forms
(species), beyond individuals. It kills "essences"
beyond "existences," the "soul" as well as the "body." It
kills collectively, not just distributively. It kills birth
as well as death. Afterward nothing of that kind either
lives or dies.
"Ought species x to
exist?" is a distributive increment in the collective
question, "Ought life on Earth to exist?" Life on Earth
cannot exist without its individuals, but a lost individual
is always reproducible, a lost species is never
reproducible. The answer to the species question is not
always the same as the answer to the collective question,
but, since life on Earth is an aggregate of many species,
the two are sufficiently related that the burden of proof
lies with those who wish deliberately to extinguish a
species and simultaneously to care for life on Earth.
One form of life has never
endangered so many others. Never before has this level of
question--superkilling by a superkiller--been deliberately
faced. Humans have more understanding than ever of the
natural world they inhabit, of the speciating processes,
more predictive power to foresee the intended and unintended
results of their actions, and more power to reverse the
undesirable consequences. The duties that such power and
vision generate no longer attach simply to individuals or
persons but are emerging duties to specific forms of life.
What is ethically callous is the maelstrom of killing and
insensitivity to forms of life and the sources producing
them. What is required is principled responsibility to the
biospheric Earth.
Human activities seem misfit
in the system. Although humans are maximizing their own
species interests, and in this respect behaving as does each
of the other species, they do not have any adaptive fitness.
They are not really fitting into the evolutionary processes
of ongoing biological conservation and elaboration. Their
cultures are not really dynamically stable in their
ecosystems. Such behavior is therefore not right. Yet
humanistic ethical systems limp when they try to prescribe
right conduct here. They seem misfits in the roles most
recently demanded of them.
If, in this world of
uncertain moral convictions, it makes any sense to claim
that one ought not to kill individuals, without
justification, it makes more sense to claim that one ought
not to superkill the species, without superjustification.
Several billion years worth of creative toil, several
million species of teeming life, have been handed over to
the care of this late-coming species in which mind has
flowered and morals have emerged. Ought not this sole moral
species do something less self-interested than count all the
produce of an evolutionary ecosystem as nothing but human
resources? Such an attitude hardly seems biologically
informed, much less ethically adequate. It is too provincial
for intelligent humanity. Life on Earth is a many
splendored thing; extinction dims its lustre. An ethics of
respect for life is urgent at the level of species.
Ecosystems
A species is what it is
where it is. No environmental ethics has found its way on
Earth until it finds an ethic for the biotic communities in
which all destinies are entwined. "A thing is right," urged
Aldo Leopold "when it tends to preserve the integrity,
stability, and beauty of the biotic community; it is wrong
when it tends otherwise." Again, we have two parts to the
ethic: first that ecosystems exist, both in the wild and in
support of culture; secondly that ecosystems ought to exist,
both for what they are in themselves and as modified by
culture. Again, we must move with care from the biological
claims to the ethical claims.
Giant forest fires raged
over Yellowstone National park in the summer of 1988,
consuming nearly a million acres, despite the efforts of a
thousand firefighters. By far the largest fires ever known
in the park, the fires seemed a disaster. But the
Yellowstone land ethic enjoins: Let nature take its course.
Let it burn! So the fires were not fought at first, but in
midsummer national authorities overrode that policy and
ordered the fires put out. Even then, weeks later, fires
continued to burn, partly because they were too big to
control, but partly too because Yellowstone personnel did
not really want the fires put out. Despite the evident
destruction of trees, shrubs, and wildlife, they believe
that fires are a good thing--even when the elk and bison
leave the park in search of food and are shot by hunters.
Fires reset succession, release nutrients, recycle
materials, renew the biotic community. (Nearby, in the Teton
wilderness, a storm blew down 15,000 acres of trees, and
some proposed that the area be de-classified as wilderness
for commercial salvage of the timber. But a similar
environmental ethics said: No, let it rot.)
Aspen are important in the
Yellowstone ecosystem. While some aspen stands are climax
and self-renewing, many are seral and give way to conifers.
Aspen groves support many birds and much wildlife,
especially the beavers, whose activities maintain the
riparian zones. Aspen are rejuvenated after fires, and the
Yellowstone land ethic wants the aspen for its critical role
in the biotic community. Elk browse the young aspen stems.
To a degree this is a good thing, since it gives elk
critical nitrogen, but in excess it is a bad thing. The elk
have no predators, since the wolves are gone, and as a
result they overpopulate. Excess elk also destroy the
willows and this in turn destroys the beavers. So, in
addition to letting fires burn, rejuvenating the aspen might
require managers to cull hundreds of elk--all for the sake
of a healthy ecosystem.
The Yellowstone ethic wishes
to restore wolves to the greater Yellowstone ecosystem. At
the level of species, this is partly for what the wolf is in
itself, but it is partly because the greater Yellowstone
ecosystem does not have its full integrity, stability, and
beauty without this majestic animal at the top of the
trophic pyramid. Restoring the wolf as a top predator would
mean suffering and death for many elk, but that would be a
good thing for the aspen and willows, for the beavers and
riparian habitat, with mixed benefits for the bighorns and
mule deer, whose food the overpopulating elk consume, but
who would also be consumed by the wolves. Restoration of
wolves would be done over the protests of ranchers who worry
about wolves eating their cattle; many of them also believe
that the wolf is a bloodthirsty killer, a bad kind.
Nevertheless, the Yellowstone ethic demands wolves, as it
does fires, in appropriate respect for life in its
ecosystem.
Letting nature take its
ecosystemic course is why the Yellowstone ethic forbade
rescuing the drowning bison, but rescued the sow grizzly
with her cubs, the latter to insure that the big predators
remain. After the bison drowned, coyotes and magpies, foxes
and ravens fed on the carcass. Later, even a grizzly bear
fed on it. All this is a good thing because the system
cycles on. On that account rescuing the whales trapped in
the winter ice seems less of a good thing, when we note that
rescuers had to drive away polar bears that attempted to eat
the dying whales.
Classical, humanistic ethics
finds ecosystems unfamiliar territory. It is difficult to
get the biology right, and, superimposed on the biology, to
get the ethics right. Fortunately, it is often evident that
human welfare depends on ecosystemic support, and in this
sense all our legislation about clean air, clean water, soil
conservation, national and state forest policy, pollution
controls, renewable resources and so forth is concerned
about ecosystem level processes. Further, humans find much
of value preserving wild ecosystems and our wilderness and
park system is impressive.
Still, a comprehensive
environmental ethics needs the best, naturalistic reasons,
as well as the good, humanistic ones, for respecting
ecosystems. Ecosystems generate and support life, keep
selection pressures high, enrich situated fitness, evolve
congruent kinds in their places with sufficient containment.
The ecologist finds that ecosystems are objectively
satisfactory communities in the sense that organismic needs
are sufficiently met for species long to survive, and the
critical ethicist finds (in a subjective judgment matching
the objective process) that such ecosystems are satisfactory
communities to which to attach duty. Our concern must be for
the fundamental unit of survival.
An ecosystem, the
conservative ethicist will say, is too low a level of
organization to be respected intrinsically. Ecosystems can
seem little more than random, statistical processes. A
forest can seem a loose collection of externally related
parts, the collection of fauna and flora a jumble, hardly a
community. The plants and animals within an ecosystem have
needs, but their interplay can seem simply a matter of
distribution and abundance, birth rates and death rates,
population densities, parasitism and predation, dispersion,
checks and balances, stochastic process. Much is not organic
at all (rain, groundwater, rocks, soil particles, air),
while some organic material is dead and decaying debris
(fallen trees, scat, humus). These things have no organized
needs. There is only catch-as-catch-can scrimmage for
nutrients and energy, a game played with loaded dice, not
really enough integrated process to call the whole a
community.
Unlike higher animals,
ecosystems have no experiences; they do not and cannot care.
Unlike plants, an ecosystem has no organized center, no
genome. It does not defend itself against injury or death.
Unlike a species, there is no ongoing telos, no
biological identity reinstantiated over time. The organismic
parts are more complex than the community whole. More
troublesome still, an ecosystem can seem a jungle where the
fittest survive, a place of contest and conflict, beside
which the organism is a model of cooperation. In animals,
the heart, liver, muscles and brain are tightly integrated,
as are the leaves, cambium, and roots in plants. But the
ecosystem community so-called is pushing and shoving between
rivals, each aggrandizing itself, or else all indifference
and haphazard juxtaposition, nothing to call forth our
admiration.
Environmental ethics must
break through the boundary posted by disoriented ontological
conservatives, who hold that only organisms are "real,"
actually existing as entities, whereas ecosystems are
nominal--just interacting individuals. Oak trees are real
but forests are nothing but collections of trees. But any
level is real if it shapes behavior on the level below it.
Thus the cell is real because that pattern shapes the
behavior of amino acids; the organism because that pattern
coordinates the behavior of hearts and lungs. The biotic
community is real because the niche shapes the morphology of
the oak trees within it. Being real at the level of
community only requires an organization that shapes the
behavior of its members.
The challenge is to find a
clear model of community and to discover an ethics for
it--better biology for better ethics. Even before the rise
of ecology, biologists began to conclude that the combative
survival of the fittest distorts the truth. The more
perceptive model is coaction in adapted fit. Predator and
prey, parasite and host, grazer and grazed are contending
forces in dynamic process where the well-being of each is
bound up with the other--coordinated (orders that couple
together) as much as heart and liver are coordinated
organically. The ecosystem supplies the coordinates through
which each organism moves, outside which the species cannot
really be located.
The community connections
are looser than the organism's internal
interconnections--but not less significant. Admiring organic
unity in organisms and stumbling over environmental
looseness is like valuing mountains and despising valleys.
The matrix the organism requires in order to survive is the
open, pluralistic ecology. Internal complexity--heart,
liver, muscles, brain--arises as a way of dealing with a
complex, tricky environment. The skin-out processes are not
just the support, they are the subtle source of the skin-in
processes. In the complete picture, the outside is as
vital as the inside. Had there been either simplicity or
lock-step concentrated unity in the environment, no
organismic unity could have evolved. Nor would it remain.
There would be less elegance in life.
To look at one level for
what is appropriate at another makes a category mistake. One
should not look for a single center or program in
ecosystems, much less for subjective experiences. Instead,
one should look for a matrix, for interconnections between
centers (individual plants and animals, dynamic lines of
speciation), for creative stimulus and open-ended potential.
Everything will be connected to many other things, sometimes
by obligate associations, more often by partial and pliable
dependencies and, among other things, there will be no
significant interactions. There will be functions in a
communal sense: shunts and criss-crossing pathways,
cybernetic subsystems and feedback loops. An order arises
spontaneously and systematically when many self-concerned
units jostle and seek their own programs, each doing their
own thing and forced into informed interaction.
An ecosystem is a
productive, projective system. Organisms defend only their
selves, with individuals defending their continuing survival
and species increasing the numbers of kinds. But the
evolutionary ecosystem spins a bigger story, limiting each
kind, locking it into the welfare of others, promoting new
arrivals, increasing kinds and the integration of kinds.
Species increase their kind; but ecosystems
increase kinds, superposing the latter increase onto the
former. Ecosystems are selective systems, as surely as
organisms are selective systems. The natural selection
comes out of the system and is imposed on the individual.
The individual is programmed to make more of its kind, but
more is going on systemically than that; the system is
making more kinds.
Communal processes--the
competition between organisms, more or less probable events,
plant and animal successions, speciation over historical
time--generate an ever-richer community. Hence the
evolutionary toil, elaborating and diversifying the biota,
that once began with no species and results today in five
million species, increasing over time the quality of lives
in the upper rungs of the tropic pyramids. One celled
organisms evolved into many-celled, highly integrated
organisms. Photosynthesis evolved and came to support
locomotion--swimming, walking, running, flight.
Stimulus-response mechanisms became complex instinctive
acts. Warm-blooded animals followed cold-blooded ones.
Complex nervous systems, conditioned behavior and learning
emerged. Sentience appeared--sight, hearing, smell, tastes,
pleasure, pain. Brains coupled with hands. Consciousness and
self-consciousness arose. Culture was superposed on nature.
These developments do not
take place in all ecosystems or at every level. Microbes,
plants, and lower animals remain, good of their kinds, and
serving continuing roles, good for other kinds. The
understories remain occupied. As a result, the quantity of
life and its diverse qualities continue--from protozoans to
primates to people. There is a push-up, lock-up, ratchet
effect that conserves the upstrokes and the outreaches. The
later we go in time the more accelerated are the forms at
the top of the tropic pyramids, the more elaborated are the
multiple tropic pyramids of Earth. There are upward arrows
over evolutionary time.
The system is a game with
loaded dice, but the loading is a prolife tendency, not mere
stochastic process. Though there is no Nature in the
singular, the system has a nature, a loading that
pluralizes, putting natures into diverse kinds,
nature1, nature2, nature3
... naturen. It does so using random elements
(in both organisms and communities), but this is a secret of
its fertility, producing steadily intensified
interdependencies and options. An ecosystem has no head,
but it has a "heading" for species diversification, support,
and richness. Though not a superorganism, it is a kind of
vital field.
Instrumental value
uses something as a means to an end; intrinsic value
is worthwhile in itself. No warbler eats insects to become
food for a falcon; the warbler defends its own life as an
end in itself and makes more warblers as she can. A life is
defended intrinsically, without further contributory
reference. But neither of these traditional terms is
satisfactory at the level of the ecosystem. Though it has
value in itself, the system does not have any value
for itself. Though a value producer, it is not a
value owner. We are no longer confronting instrumental
value, as though the system were of value instrumentally as
a fountain of life. Nor is the question one of intrinsic
value, as though the system defended some unified form of
life for itself. We have reached something for which we
need a third term: systemic value. Duties arise in
encounter with the system that projects and protects these
member components in biotic community.
Ethical conservatives, in
the humanist sense, will say that ecosystems are of value
only because they contribute to human experiences. But that
mistakes the last chapter for the whole story, one fruit for
the whole plant. Humans count enough to have the right to
flourish there, but not so much that they have the right to
degrade or shut down ecosystems, not at least without a
burden of proof that there is an overriding cultural gain.
Those who have traveled part way into environmental ethics
will say that ecosystems are of value because they
contribute to animal experiences or to organismic life. But
the really conservative, radical view sees that the
stability, integrity, and beauty of biotic communities is
what is most fundamentally to be conserved. In a
comprehensive ethics of respect for life, we ought to set
ethics at the level of ecosystems alongside classical,
humanistic ethics.
Value theory
In practice the ultimate
challenge of environmental ethics is the conservation of
life on Earth. In principle the ultimate challenge is a
value theory profound enough to support that ethic. In
nature there is negentropic construction in dialectic with
entropic teardown, a process for which we hardly yet have an
adequate scientific, much less a valuational theory. Yet
this is nature's most striking feature, one that ultimately
must be valued and of value. In one sense nature is
indifferent to mountains, rivers, fauna, flora, forests and
grasslands. But in another sense nature has bent toward
making and remaking these projects, millions of kinds, for
several billion years.
These performances are worth
noticing--remarkable, memorable--and not just because of
their tendencies to produce something else, certainly not
merely because of their tendency to produce this noticing in
certain recent subjects--our human selves. These events are
loci of value as products of systemic nature in its
formative processes. The splendors of Earth do not simply
lie in their roles as human resources, supports of culture,
or stimulators of experience. The most plausible account
will find some programmatic evolution toward value, and not
because it ignores Darwin but because it heeds his principle
of natural selection and deploys this into a selection
exploring new niches and elaborating kinds, even a selection
upslope toward higher values, at least along some trends
within some ecosystems. How do we humans come to be charged
up with values, if there was and is nothing in nature
charging us up so? A systematic environmental ethics does
not wish to believe in the special creation of values, nor
in their dumfounding epigenesis. Let them evolve. Let
nature carry value.
The notion that nature is a
value carrier is ambiguous. Much depends on a thing being
more or less structurally congenial for the carriage. We
value a thing to discover that we are under the sway of its
valence, inducing our behavior. It has among its
"strengths" (Latin: valeo, be strong) this capacity
to carry value. This potential cannot always be of the
empty sort that a glass has for carrying water. It is often
pregnant fullness. Some of the values that nature carries
are up to us, our assignment. But fundamentally there are
powers in nature that move to us and through us.
There is no value without an
evaluator. So runs a well-entrenched dogma. Humans clearly
evaluate their world; sentient animals may also. But plants
cannot evaluate their environment; they have no options and
make no choices. A fortiori, species and ecosystems,
Earth and Nature cannot be bona fide evaluators. One can
always hang on to the claim that value, like a tickle or
remorse, must be felt to be there. Its esse is
percipi. Nonsensed value is nonsense. There are no
thoughts without a thinker, no percepts without a perceiver,
no deeds without a doer, no targets without an aimer.
Such resolute subjectivists
cannot be defeated by argument, although they can be driven
toward analyticity. That theirs is a retreat to definition
is difficult to expose, because they seem to cling so
closely to inner experience. They are reporting, on this
hand, how values always excite us. They are giving, on that
hand, a stipulative definition. That is how they choose to
use the word "value."
If value arrives only with
consciousness, experiences where humans find value there
have to be dealt with as appearances of various sorts. The
value has to be relocated in the valuing subject's
creativity as a person meets a valueless world, or even a
valuable one--one able to be valued--but which
before the human bringing of value ability contains only
possibility and not any actual value. Value can only be
extrinsic to nature, never intrinsic to it.
But the valuing subject in
an otherwise valueless world is an insufficient premise for
the experienced conclusions of those who respect all life.
Conversion to a biological view seems truer to world
experience and more logically compelling. Here the order of
knowing reverses--and also enhances--the order of being.
This too is a perspective, but ecologically better
informed. Science has been steadily showing how the
consequents (life, mind) are built on their precedents
(energy, matter), however much they overleap them. Life and
mind appear where they did not before exist, and with this
levels of value emerge that did not before exist. But that
gives no reason to say that all value is an irreducible
emergent at the human (or upper animal) level. A
comprehensive environmental ethics reallocates value across
the whole continuum. Value increases in the emergent
climax, but is continuously present in the composing
precedents. The system is value-able, able to produce value.
Human evaluators are among its products.
Some value depends on
subjectivity, yet all value is generated within the
geosystemic and ecosystemic pyramid. Systemically, value
fades from subjective to objective value, but also fans out
from the individual to its role and matrix. Things do not
have their separate natures merely in and for themselves,
but they face outward and co-fit into broader natures.
Value-in-itself is smeared out to become value-in-togetherness.
Value seeps out into the system, and we lose our capacity to
identify the individual as the sole locus of value.
Intrinsic value, that of an
individual "for what it is in itself," becomes problematic
in a holistic web. True, the system produces such values
more and more with its evolution of individuality and
freedom. Yet to decouple this from the biotic, communal
system is to make value too internal and elementary; this
forgets relatedness and externality. Every intrinsic value
has leading and trailing and's pointing to value from
which it comes and toward which it moves. Adapted fitness
makes individualistic value too system independent.
Intrinsic value is a part in a whole, not to be fragmented
by valuing it in isolation.
Everything is good in a role,
in a whole, although we can speak of objective intrinsic
goodness wherever a point event--a trillium--defends a good
(its life) in itself. We can speak of subjective intrinsic
goodness when such an event registers as a point experience,
at which point humans pronounce both their experience and
what it is of good without need to enlarge their focus.
Neither the trilliums nor the human judges of it require for
their respective valuings any further contributory reference.
When eaten by foragers or in
death resorbed into humus, the trillium has its value
destroyed, transformed into instrumentality. The system is
a value transformer where form and being, process and
reality, fact and value are inseparably joined. Intrinsic
and instrumental values shuttle back and forth,
parts-in-wholes and wholes-in-parts, local details of value
embedded in global structures, gems in their settings, and
their setting-situation a corporation where value cannot
stand alone. Every good is in community.
In environmental ethics
one's beliefs about nature, which are based upon but exceed
science, have everything to do with beliefs about duty. The
way the world is informs the way it ought to
be. We always shape our values in significant measure in
accord with our notion of the kind of universe that we live
in, and this drives our sense of duty. Our model of reality
implies a model of conduct. Differing models sometimes imply
similar conduct, but often they do not. A model in which
nature has no value apart from human preferences will imply
different conduct from one where nature projects fundamental
values, some objective and others that further require human
subjectivity superposed on objective nature.
This evaluation is not
scientific description; hence not ecology per se, but
metaecology. No amount of research can verify that,
environmentally, the right is the optimum biotic community.
Yet ecological description generates this valuing of nature,
endorsing the systemic rightness. The transition from is
to good and thence to ought occurs here; we
leave science to enter the domain of evaluation, from which
an ethic follows.
What is ethically puzzling
and exciting is that an ought is not so much
derived from an is as discovered simultaneously
with it. As we progress from descriptions of fauna and
flora, of cycles and pyramids, of autotrophs coordinated
with heterotrophs, of stability and dynamism, on to
intricacy, planetary opulence and interdependence, to unity
and harmony with oppositions in counterpoint and synthesis,
organisms evolved within and satisfactorily fitting their
communities, arriving at length at beauty and goodness, it
is difficult to say where the natural facts leave off and
where the natural values appear. For some at least, the
sharp is/ought dichotomy is gone; the values seem to
be there as soon as the facts are fully in, and both alike
properties of the system.
There is something
overspecialized about an ethic, held by the dominant class
of Homo sapiens, that regards the welfare of only one
of several million species as an object and beneficiary of
duty. If this requires a paradigm change about the sorts of
things to which duty can attach, so much the worse for those
humanistic ethics no longer functioning in, nor suited to,
their changing environment. The anthropocentrism associated
with them was fiction anyway. There is something Newtonian,
not yet Einsteinian, besides something morally naive, about
living in a reference frame where one species takes itself
as absolute and values everything else relative to its
utility. If true to their specific epithet, ought not
Homo sapiens value this host of life as something with a
claim to care in its own right?
Only the human species
contains moral agents, but perhaps conscience on such an
Earth ought not be used to exempt every other form of life
from consideration, with the resulting paradox that the sole
moral species acts only in its collective self-interest
toward all the rest. Is not the ultimate philosophical task
the discovery of a whole great ethic that knows the human
place under the sun? |